Chapter2

Axiom

  • Axiom 2.1. \(0\) is a natural number.

  • Axiom 2.2. If \(n\) is a natural number, then \(n\pp\) is also a natural number.

  • Axiom 2.3. \(0\) is not the sucessor of any natural number; i.e., we have \(n\pp\neq0\) for every natural number \(n\).

  • Axiom 2.4. Different natural numbers must have different successors; i.e., if \(n,~m\) are natural numbers and \(n\neq m\), then \(n\pp\neq m\pp\). Equivalently, if \(n\pp=n\pp\), then we must have \(n=m\).

  • Axiom 2.5 (Principle of mathematical induction). Let \(P(n)\) be any property pertaining to a natural number \(n\). Suppose that \(P(0)\) is true, and suppose that whenever \(P(n)\) is true, \(P(n\pp)\) is also true. Then \(P(n)\) is true for every natural number \(n\).

Definitions

  • Definition 2.2.1 (Addition of natural numbers). Let \(m\) be a natural number. To add zero to \(m\), we define \(0+m:=m\). Now suppose inductively that we have defined how to add \(n\) to \(m\). Then we can add \(n\pp\) to \(m\) by defining \((n\pp)+m:=(n+m)\pp\)

  • Definition 2.2.7 (Positive natural numbers). A natural number \(n\) is said to be \(positive\) iff it is not equal to \(0\).

  • Definition 2.2.11 (Ordering of the natural numbers). Let \(n\) and \(m\) be natural numbers. We say that \(n\) is greater than or equal to \(m\), and write \(n\geq m\) or \(m\leq n\), iff we have \(n=m+a\) for some natural number \(a\). We say that \(n\) is strictly greater than \(m\), and write \(n>m\) or \(m<n\), iff \(n\geq m\) and \(n\neq m\).

  • Definition 2.3.1 (Multiplication of natural numbers). Let \(m\) be a natural number. To multiply zero to \(m\), we define \(0 \times m := 0\). Now suppose inductively that we have defined how to multiply \(n\) to \(m\). Then we can multiply \(n\pp\) to \(m\) by defining \((n\pp) \times m := (n \times m) + m\).

  • Definition 2.3.11 (Exponentiation for natural numbers). Let \(m\) be a natural number. To raise \(m\) to the power \(0\), we define \(m^0:=1\); in particular, we define \(0^0:=1\). Now suppose recursively that \(m^n\) has been defined for some natural number \(n\), then we define \(m^{n\pp}:=m^n\times m\).

Propositions

  • Lemma 2.2.2. For any natural number \(n\), \(n+0=n\).

  • Lemma 2.2.3. For any natural number \(n\) and \(m\), \(n+(m\pp)=(n+m)\pp\).

  • Proposition 2.2.4 (Addition is commutative). For any natural numbers \(n\) and \(m\), \(n+m=m+n\).

  • Proposition 2.2.5 (Addition is associative). For any natural numbers \(a,b,c\), we have \((a+b)+c=a+(b+c)\).

  • Proposition 2.2.6 (Cancellation law). Let \(a,b,c\) be natural numbers such that \(a+b=a+c\). Then we have \(b=c\).

  • Proposition 2.2.8 If \(a\) is positive and \(b\) is a natural number, then \(a+b\) is positive (and hence \(b+a\) is also, by Proposition 2.2.4

  • Corollary 2.2.9 If \(a\) and \(b\) are natural numbers such that \(a+b=0\), then \(a=0\) and \(b=0\).

  • Lemma 2.2.10. Let \(a\) be a positive number. Then there exists exactly one natural number \(b\) such that \(b\pp=a\).

  • Propostion 2.2.12 (Basic properties of order for natural numbers) let \(a,b,c\) be natural numbers. Then

    • (a) (Order is reflexive) \(a\geq a\).

    • (b) (Order is transitive) If \(a\geq b\) and \(b\geq c\), then \(a\geq c\).

    • (c) (Order is anti-symmetric) If \(a\geq b\) and \(b\geq a\), then \(a=b\).

    • (d) (Addition preserves order) \(a\geq b\) only and only if \(a+c\geq b+c\).

    • (e) \(a<b\) if and only if \(a\pp\leq b\).

    • (f) \(a<b\) if and only if \(b=a+d\) for some positive number \(a\).

    • \(Proof\). See Exercise 2.2.3.

  • Proposition 2.2.13 (Trichotomy of order for natural numbers). Let \(a\) and \(b\) be natural numbers. Then excactly one of the following statements is true: \(a<b, a=b\), or \(a>b\).

  • Proposition 2.2.14 (Strong principle of induction). Let \(m_0\) be a natural number, and let \(P(m)\) be a property pertaining to an arbitrary natural number \(m\). Suppose that for each \(m\geq m_0\), we have the following implication: if \(P(m')\) is true for all natural numbers \(m_0\leq m'<m\), then \(P(m)\) is also true. (In particular, this means that \(P(m_0)\) is true, since in this case the hypothesis is vacuous.) Then we can conclude that \(P(m)\) is true for all natrual numbers \(m\geq m_0\).

  • Lemma 2.3.2 (Multiplication is commutative). Let \(n\) and \(m\) be natural numbers. Then \(n \times m = m \times n\).

  • Lemma 2.3.3 (Positive natural numbers have no zero divisors). Let \(n, m\) be natural numbers. Then \(n \times m = 0\) if and only if at least one of \(n, m\) is equal to zero. In particular, if \(n\) and \(m\) are both positive, then \(nm\) is also positive.

  • Propostion 2.3.4 (Distributive law). For any natural numbers \(a,b,c\), we have \(a(b+c)=ab+ac\) and \((b+c)a=ba+ca\).

  • Propostion 2.3.5 (Multiplication is associative). /For any natural numbers \(a,b,c\), we ahve \((a \times b) \times c = a \times (b \times c)\).

  • Propostion 2.3.6 (Multiplication preserves order). If \(a,b\) are natural numbers such that \(a<b\), and \(c\) is positive, then \(ac<bc\).

  • Corollary 2.3.7 (Cancellation law). Let \(a,b,c\) be natural numbers such that \(ac=bc\) and \(c\) is non-zero. Then \(a=b\).

  • Propostion 2.3.9 (Euclidean algorithm). Let \(n\) be a natural number, and let \(q\) be a positive number. Then there exist natrual numbers \(m,r\) such that \(0\leq r<q\) and \(n=mq+r\).

Exercises

Links to this page
  • Chapter3
    Axiom 3.7. (Infinity). There exists a set \(\mathbb{N}\), whose elements are called natural numbers, as well as an object \(0\) in \(\mathbb{N}\), and an object \(n\pp\) assigned to every natural number \(n\in\mathbb{N}\), such that the Peano axioms (Axioms 2.1-2.5) hold.
  • Axiom 3.7
    Axiom 3.7. (Infinity). There exists a set \(\mathbb{N}\), whose elements are called natural numbers, as well as an object \(0\) in \(\mathbb{N}\), and an object \(n\pp\) assigned to every natural number \(n\in\mathbb{N}\), such that the Peano axioms (Axioms 2.1-2.5) hold.